What is the why in your life?” That was the question asked by Mark Wilson, lead
pastor at the Fowlerville United Brethren Church, at the recent meeting of the
Fowlerville Business Association. Pastor Wilson was a guest speaker at the
morning session and the overall theme of his talk was “Leadership: Intentional
Living in Business & Life.”
In his discussion on what motivates us in
our work as well as our overall life—what we perceive as our purpose and what
energizes us—he noted that many people have great ideas but fail to follow
through with actions. In pursuing a more purposeful, fulfilling, and rewarding
life, not only do we need to dream boldly, but at some point we ought to act
upon those aspirations.
During his talk, Pastor Wilson asked a
number of questions designed to draw his audience into the discussion both with
our answers and our back-and-forth comments. It proved an effective tactic,
with several persons (including yours truly) offering our thoughts.
One of the questions that got tossed into
this cauldron of discourse was whether results, in and of themselves, matter or
if it’s important that we also possess good motives when taking an action.
“This is the stuff of philosophy,” I piped
up.
To illustrate my assertion, I posed the
question, “If the outcome of your action proves beneficial, but your underlying
intent was not praiseworthy, would the result be considered an ethical action?
Or is motive also an important factor?”
Most of those in attendance, responding
more to Pastor Wilson’s question on finding our why and less to my abrupt detour into philosophical speculation,
felt that motive mattered.
Pastor Wilson, in his talk, listed the “Five
Benefits to Finding Your Why,” and
they would seem to support the attendees answer that motive matters..
Knowing
Your Why Gives You Freedom—You
have to find yourself in order to lose yourself. Understanding your why gives you freedom to serve other
people and make a significant contribution to your world.
Living
Out Your Why Gives You Confidence—Our
why creates security and comfort for
you in everything you do. When you have confidence, other people take notice of
you and want to figure out why you’re different.
Layering
Your Why Gives You Momentum—There’s
a deep connection between your strengths and your why. The more you work out of
yours strengths in pursuit of your why, the more you increase both.
Consistently
Living Your Why Gives You Impact—Living out your why on a daily basis creates a
compounding effect for your reputation and results, giving you a greater impact
on your world.
Knowing Your Why Gives You Longevity—Your why is
your motivation to make every day count, no matter your age. It provides you
with the necessary fuel to live until you die.
While you could classify the message we
heard as a motivational or inspirational speech, the kind of self-improvement
pep talk that is common at business meetings and seminars, it’s safe to say
that Pastor Wilson’s talk possessed an underlying moral component.
He wasn’t urging us to find our life’s
purpose so we could more ruthlessly exploit our customers, or drive our competitors
out of business, or pursue a goal of accumulating as many worldly riches as
possible. So (if I might put words in his mouth), the manner in which we
conduct our business and our lives—the goals we have and the dreams we harbor--matter
both in how we envision them and what course of action we take to realize them.
So, in response to my rhetorical question,
a person’s intent or underlying motive matters as much as the consequences of
our ensuing actions.
Case closed?
Well, not with philosophical speculation.
Allow me to pose another question: How do we
go about determining how to live a moral life? What criteria or guideposts
should we utilize in making our choices and conducting our activities? In
trying to find our why, there is obviously
the personal component. Yet, no man is an
island. We inhabit a larger world,
and many of our fellow humans, past and present, hold views that are not always
in line with our own.
Also, in many instances, deciding what’s right
from wrong, good from bad, and moral from immoral would seem (and is) a
no-brainer. But not every situation or fork-in-the-road presents a clear-cut
choice. People of character might judge
the circumstances differently and be inclined to pursue a direction contrary to
our choice. Are we right, good, and moral, while they are wrong, bad, and
immoral?
ANYONE
TAKING AN INTRODUCTORY COURSE IN PHILOSOPHY will soon come to the chapter
on ethics (or moral philosophy). This is the study of moral judgments,
including what is virtuous or base, just or unjust, morally right or wrong,
morally good or bad or evil, and morally proper and improper.
The question
I posed at the meeting of whether a good outcome would offset a self-centered
motive—the relationship between intentions and consequences—would comfortably fall
within the realm of ethics.
Moral philosophy has been divided into five
main frameworks. Two of the more familiar ones are:
Divine-command
ethics: What should I do? What God ordains. A person’s particular religion
or spiritual outlook serves as the guiding light.
Relativism:
What should I do? Whatever my society feels is correct. My actions should
reflect the cultural norms of where I live and how I was brought up.
We prefer to think that what is ethical or
unethical or what moral or immoral as universal and fixed, yet in many
instances our religious faith or cultural norms influence our judgment. And
while the tenants of different faiths and the mores of different societies have
much in common, we well know there are differences.
Three other frameworks are:
Consequentialism: What should
I do? Whatever has the more beneficial consequences, either for me or for the
greater society.
Deontological
ethics: What should I do? What I see as my moral duty regardless of
consequences.
Virtue
ethics: What should I do? What a
virtuous person would do. My actions should be the by-product of training
myself though self-examination to be the kind of person who behaves and acts in
a moral manner.
I think finding your why might fall into this final framework, along with the Divine-command
heading.
In that introductory course, the student
will very likely study two of the better known and influential ethical systems
that were put forth and have had an impact: Utilitarianism, introduced by Jeremy
Bentham, an English philosopher and social reformer (1748-1832), and fine-tuned
by his protégé John Stuart Mill, and the Categorical Imperative set for a
treatise by the 18th century German philosopher Immanuel Kant.
Kant and Bentham were part of the European Age of Reason. In this country, the
Declaration of Independence (with its assertion self-evident truths) and the
U.S. Constitution (with its checks and balances and separation of governmental
powers) were byproducts of this period of intellectual ferment.
Utilitarianism
states that the rightness or wrongness of an action should be judged by its
consequences and that what is ethical is an action or outcome that promotes the
greatest happiness (or good) for the greatest number. However, your own
happiness is not more important morally than that of others.
Bentham
equated happiness with pleasure and unhappiness with pain. “Nature,” he said, “has
placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign masters, pain and
pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we ought to do, as well as
determine what we shall do.”
Mill,
who refined the tenants of this ethical system, stated that a moral principle
by its very nature singles out no one for preferential treatment. With that
qualification in mind, he wrote, “as between his own happiness and that of
others,” the utilitarian is required “to be as strictly impartial as a
disinterested and benevolent spectator.” Mill also felt that certain pleasures
are “inherently better” than others and are to be preferred.
One
of the difficulties of this system (in my mind) is that the terms pleasure and
pain are easy enough to comprehend as a physical sensation that each and all of
us experience in the course of our daily lives. However, we do not tend to
regard these sensations in moral terms, unless it would be the anguish of guilt
or regret and the warm glow we feel when praised for a good deed. To think of
pleasure for society in general as a measurable moral good and pain as a means
for determining a social ill is difficult to grasp. How exactly can this be
done?
Looking past that stumbling block, what
utilitarianism is stating is that when all is said and done, outcome trumps
motive. Or as Spock often said in Star
Trek, “The needs of the many outweigh those of the few.”
The Utilitarians were also pointing out the
reality that in our daily living, we understandably embrace choices that bring
us pleasure and happiness and shun that which cause pain and unhappiness. Their
notion of ethics, to some extent, is a reflection of that human behavior.
I had
this in mind when I asked at the meeting: “If
the outcome of your action proves beneficial, but your underlying intent was not
praiseworthy, would the result be considered an ethical action? Or is motive
also an important factor?”
Under the utilitarian system, the answer would
seem to be “yes.”
Bentham’s ethical system, when transposed
onto the realm of political philosophy (a consideration of what governmental
actions are moral and just), would seem to give preference to majority rule, or
certainly to what is judged to be in the best interest for society in general.
Yet in his social-reform efforts, for which he was equally famous, Bentham was
a champion of individual rights. His advocacy resulted in the development of
welfare, and he advocated on behalf of individual freedom, freedom of
expression, equal rights for women, the right of women to divorce, the
decriminalization of homosexual acts, and the abolition of slavery.
Kant,
whose work predated the Utilitarians, felt a moral rule “is something that
holds without exception and that it is universal in application. Kant also felt
that determining a moral principle could be done through rational means, or the
use of logic.
The term he
made famous is Categorical Imperative. This would be “a moral law that is
unconditional or absolute for all agents, the validity or claim of which does
not depend on an ulterior motive or end.”
The litmus test he prescribed is “to act
always in such a way that you could, rationally, will the principle of which
you act to be a universal law.”
An example used in a textbook to illustrate
Kant’s prescription is: If you are tempted to cheat on a test, then the
principle you would presumably employ as a rationale is that securing a passing
grade is of such benefit that it makes it permissible to cheat. However, if
this principle (cheating) was to become a universal law, and everyone did it,
then the value of the grade would be diminished.
Kant also stated that an act is “just” or
“unjust” without any regard to the consequences of that same action. So, under this system, neither your personal
motivation nor the outcome of your actions is the deciding factor: A moral principle
is either a moral principle or it is not.
At first
glance, Kant seems a more understandable approach to ethics. Clear, concise, no
ambiguity. But, as they say, “the devil
is in the details” or as my late father was fond of saying, “The road to hell
is paved with good intentions.”
Most people
feel that lying is wrong, but many of us would say that a white lie that spares
someone’s feeling is OK. But what if our lie resulted in a positive outcome?
The Utilitarians would likely be supportive if it was deemed to be the
“greatest good (or brought the greatest happiness or pleasure) for the greatest
number.” Kant’s Categorical Imperative would be a trickier proposition.
The problem
with Kant, when you start applying his ethical system to broader-based,
real-life situations and considerations, the one-size-fits-all formula can
cause unintended consequences and furthermore, it doesn’t matter.
For example,
the impartial justice of mandatory prison sentences could be viewed as a
Categorical Imperative. But this approach takes away a judge’s discretionary power
and ignores extenuating circumstances and the whole element of good behavior
and individual rehabilitation as a reward. The varieties of individuals are
ignored, and everyone is viewed as a common denominator.
The result in
Michigan is overcrowded prisons and an increasing expense to the state budget.
Questions raised by mandatory sentences for certain crimes include: Is it good
social policy (and is it just) to offer no hope to prisoners for early release
regardless of good behavior and a genuine effort to reform themselves? And is
it prudent, not to mention ethical, to have a policy that puts an increasing
percentage of our population behind bars?
Has our list
of punishable offenses become too numerous and administration of justice too
harsh? Are we casting too wide of a net? Are we using punishment as retribution
without any potential for mercy or leniency?
On the other
hand, is justice served if different people are punished differently for the
committing the same or a similar crime? Is it fair that one prisoner is treated
differently than another? Is it fair to the victims?
Kant would
say one thing, the Utilitarians another.
As I said,
“This is the stuff of philosophy.”
The nuances, gray
areas, and ambiguities of ethics can be an interesting and compelling pursuit;
more so if approached with the realization that not everything is always clear-cut
and easily judged. It requires you to be a benevolent spectator in weighing
your own opinions against others and to act with the question in mind: What
would happen if my decision was a universal law, applicable to everyone, not
just for my benefit?
Trying to
find the why, whether for the inner
self or in the world we live in, is not necessarily straight forward and clear
cut. It can--and maybe should be--a long and winding road.
I guess you
could say that trying to find that why
is my why.
No comments:
Post a Comment